娇色导航

Skip to content
 

Blog post Part of special issue: Reimagining a curriculum for teacher knowledge

Are you experienced?

'An honest engagement with Dewey鈥檚 theory of experience can provide educators with useful questions about how to create meaningful educational experiences.'

Kevin Smith, Senior Lecturer at Cardiff University

In 1938, John Dewey wrote Experience and Education to clarify misconceptions about the conceptualisation of 鈥榩rogressive education鈥. In it, he argued for the need for an approach to education based on a 鈥榯heory of experience鈥. This emphasis on experience has been celebrated by some, and vilified by others. For example, when referring to Dewey鈥檚 views on experiential education and democratic living, Mortimer Adler 鈥 a contemporary of Dewey鈥 argued that 鈥榙emocracy has much more to fear from the mentality of its teachers than from the nihilism of Hitler鈥 (Shapiro, 1995, p.79).

Current criticisms, like Christodoulou鈥檚 in Seven Myths 娇色导航 Education (2014), argue that Dewey opposed 鈥榝acts and understanding鈥 (p.16), and insinuate that Dewey dismissed knowledge, teacher expertise and authority. Christodoulou continues by saying that Dewey 鈥榩raised methods where the child鈥檚 own inclinations and interests were allowed to determine the education process鈥 (2014, p.28), suggesting that learning activities were determined by pupils鈥 unrestrained wants and desires. However, even a quick scan of Experience and Education will show that Dewey was supremely concerned with both the acquisition of knowledge and carefully organised experiences managed by expert teachers. Here is just one example.

鈥楴o experience is educative that does not tend both to knowledge of more facts and entertaining of more ideas and to a better, a more orderly, arrangement of them. It is not true that organization is a principle foreign to experience.鈥 (Dewey, 1938, p. 82)

Subsequent misinterpretations of Dewey have led to the word 鈥榚xperience鈥 becoming an embattled term in today鈥檚 educational discourse (Alexander, 1987), but an honest engagement with Dewey鈥檚 theory of experience can provide educators with useful questions about how to create meaningful educational experiences.

‘For Dewey, a continuity of experience leads to growth, but not all experiences are equal. Differentiating educative experiences from miseducative ones requires teachers鈥 expertise in ensuring pupils experience the right kind of growth.’

Dewey鈥檚 theory of experience is part of his attempt to move beyond the dualism of objectivism and relativism. In Experience and Education, he sets out two criteria for experience: continuity and interaction. The principle of continuity rests on the assumption that 鈥榚very experience enacted and undergone modifies the one who acts and undergoes, while this modification affects, whether we wish it or not, the quality of subsequent experiences鈥 (1938, p. 35). For Dewey, a continuity of experience leads to growth, but not all experiences are equal. Differentiating educative experiences from miseducative ones requires teachers鈥 expertise in ensuring pupils experience the right kind of growth (or growth in the right direction).

鈥楨very experience is a moving force. Its value can be judged only on the ground of what it moves toward and into. The greater maturity of experience which should belong to the adult as educator puts him [sic] in a position to evaluate each experience of the young in a way in which the one having the less mature experience cannot do. It is then the business of the educator to see in what direction an experience is heading. There is no point in his being more mature if, instead of using his greater insight to help organize the conditions of the experience of the immature, he throws away his insight. Failure to take the moving force of an experience into account so as to judge and direct it on the ground of what it is moving into means disloyalty to the principle of experience itself.鈥 (Dewey, 1938, p. 35)

In discussing 鈥榠nteraction鈥 鈥 or 鈥榯ransaction鈥, as Dewey later called it 鈥 Biesta (2014) writes, 鈥榚ducation is neither about getting the curriculum into the child nor about the child just doing anything, but about establishing a productive and meaningful connection between the two鈥 (p. 31). Similar to Freire (another regularly misunderstood theorist), Dewey鈥檚 concerns are largely epistemological, arguing that 鈥榯raditional鈥 education fails to acknowledge relational aspects of knowledge construction 鈥 how pupils come to know the world both cognitively and socioculturally.聽 Dewey was concerned with knowledge聽补苍诲听the聽relationship聽between the聽knower聽补苍诲听knowledge. He wrote the problem with 鈥渢raditional鈥 education was 鈥渘ot that it emphasized the external conditions that enter into the control of the experiences but that it paid so little attention to the internal factors which also decide what kind of experience is had鈥 (1938 p.42).

For Biesta (2014), Dewey鈥檚 work

鈥樷eans the end of the idea of knowledge as a picture of reality and instead puts forward the suggestion that our knowledge is always about relationships between actions and consequences. While this does mean that knowledge is a construction, it is not a construction happening somewhere in our head, but a construction 鈥榠n transaction鈥, which means that knowledge is both constructed and real.鈥 (Biesta, 2014, p. 44)

This view is not hostile to 鈥榝acts’, 鈥榢nowledge鈥 or teachers鈥 authority or expertise 鈥 far from it. It does, however, require educators and pupils to consider 鈥榢nowing鈥 beyond the limits of dualism: not, Biesta warns, as an 鈥樏糱er-truth鈥 or metanarrative, but 鈥榓s an attempt to address a very specific problem鈥 (2014, p. 45). In this case, the question could be about how to differentiate between miseducative experiences and meaningful, educative experiences for pupils and teachers alike.

References

Alexander, T. M. (1987). John Dewey鈥檚 Theory of Art, Experience & Nature. The Horizons of Feeling. Albany: State University of New York Press.

Biesta, G. (2014). Pragmatising the curriculum: Bringing knowledge back into the curriculum conversation, but via pragmatism. Curriculum Journal, 25(1), 29鈥49. https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/09585176.2013.874954

Christodoulou, D. (2014). Seven Myths 娇色导航 Education. Routledge: London.

Dewey, J. (1938). Experience and Education. New York: Phi Delta Kappa.

Shapiro, E. (1995). Letters of Sidney Hook: Democracy, Communism and the Cold War. New York: M. E. Sharpe Inc.